In recent decades, American healthcare has occupied a central place in public discourse. The cornerstone piece of legislation in President Barack Obama’s time in office, the Affordable Care Act, has dominated discussions of access to healthcare and health insurance since its passage into law. President Donald Trump pushed for legislation that repealed portions of the Act but never articulated an alternative vision, infamously noting during a 2024 presidential debate that he had “concepts of a plan” for a replacement. Current Secretary of Health and Human Services, Robert F. Kennedy Jr., launched a failed presidential campaign focusing not on insurance or healthcare access, but instead championing a concept we will call “medical freedom.”
At the heart of medical freedom is the idea that people ought to be allowed to make choices about healthcare free from external interference. This view seems to consist of (at least) two components.
First, the negative component; that people should be free from government mandated treatment. Specifically, proponents of medical freedom argue against preventative treatments such as vaccinations. Although energized by vaccine policy in the wake of COVID-19, this idea has its roots in pushback against smallpox inoculation in the late 18th century and anti-vaccination movements in the 19th and 20th centuries. As with the historical cases, members of the current medical freedom movement view “vaccine mandates” as infringing upon their fundamental liberties, be they religious or personal, and instead seek alternative remedies or treatments for infectious disease.
(It is worth noting, though, that the government cannot mandate vaccines. Competent adults generally have the right to refuse medical treatment. However, access to some goods and organizations may require vaccination; generally students in public school must be vaccinated against common illnesses [although a vast majority of states allow for religious and/or personal exemptions], members of the military must be vaccinated against many infectious diseases, etc. So perhaps we should better understand this component as objecting to the government incentivizing any treatment.)
The idea of alternative remedies links to the positive component; that people ought to have the right to access their preferred treatments without government intervention. This is a relatively new idea, especially compared to the negative component. The federal government only began regulating drugs in the 20th century with the passage of the Pure Food and Drug Act. The law primarily required accurate labeling of products and disclosure of addictive or dangerous ingredients. In 1936, Congress passed the Federal Food, Drug and Cosmetic Act, which granted the Federal Drug Administration greater regulatory authority, including the ability to ban substances and require pre-market testing of drugs.
Both components of this freedom – the positive and the negative – seem to rely on the moral principle of autonomy, the idea that individuals have the right to make informed choices regarding themselves and their body. This right suggests it is wrong to interfere with someone if they make such a choice when sufficiently informed. Others, specifically the government, should seek only to provide information.
But there seems to be an incoherence within the autonomy-grounded medical freedom movement when placed in the context of other policies favored by the movement, at least as enacted by Kennedy thus far as HHS secretary. This incoherence gives rise to a dilemma: Either the freedoms are (nearly) absolute, in which case the movement should focus regulations primarily on providing consumers with information about products, or the freedoms are not (nearly) absolute and incursion upon them may be justified. The trouble for the proponent of medical freedom being that, once we begin condoning incursions, this may justify the very policies members of the movement rail against.
What would regulation look like if we treated these freedoms as unlimited? It seems that regulations would primarily serve to ensure that citizens are fully informed about drugs and other products they are consuming, insofar as they relate to health. Regulation would simply serve to facilitate autonomous decision-making. Give the citizenry as much information about the products on the market as you can, then let them choose for themselves.
However, members of the medical freedom movement often favor policies that work against consumer information. Organizations such as the National Health Federation stress that consumers have the unrestricted right to access dietary supplements. But in the U.S., dietary supplements occupy a different legal category than pharmaceuticals. Makers of dietary supplements must accurately label the contents of their product. However, unlike pharmaceuticals, makers of dietary supplements do not have to provide substantial evidence about purported benefits of their products. Further, manufacturers are not required to provide dosing information. Yet even common nutrients may produce adverse outcomes in high doses. Earlier this year, children in Texas were treated for Vitamin A toxicity when admitted for measles. Kennedy had previously instructed the CDC to change measles guidance to mention vitamin A as a treatment.
Thus, at least in the current legal framework, the medical freedom movement’s emphasis on dietary supplements actually inhibits, rather than supports, autonomous decision-making. Consumers have lesser access to information about these products than about prescription drugs, thus limiting their ability to make fully informed decisions.
Further, other policies favored by members of the medical freedom movement restrict choices that consumers can make. For instance, in April the FDA announced that it is working with industry to phase out synthetic food dyes, including Allura Red AC, more commonly known as Red 40. However, the Environmental Protection Agency lists Red 40 as “verified to be of low concern,” the World Health Organization finds that Red 40 “does not present a health concern,” and the European Food Advisory Committee concludes that there is limited evidence for a link between Red 40 and behavioral issues in children, a claim commonly cited in arguments against the substance.
Still, working to remove products like synthetic dyes seems like good policy. Even if there is little evidence suggesting that synthetic dyes such as Red 40 lead to adverse outcomes, precaution would justify eliminating them; we stand to gain very little by using them, so avoiding the risk, however remote, seems worth it.
The issue, though, is that this policy is in tension with autonomy. By working to remove synthetic dyes, the regulatory system is forcing a precautionary choice onto consumers that may not otherwise choose it. Even if sensible policy, it directly interferes with free consumer choice.
So, the medical freedom movement has an internal tension with the principle of autonomy in two ways. First, by stressing the freedom to access supplements, the movement inhibits the ability for consumers to make informed choices. Second, by adopting precautionary policies, the movement limits consumer choice.
Of course, one might defend the movement by arguing that precautionary policies are advisable. They might simply admit that, although we are not maximizing freedom, the benefits to public health are worth restricting at least some options.
This is an excellent response. Yet it cannot give the advocate of medical freedom everything. It may require abandoning the commitment to supplement access; a precautionary approach would demand greater scrutiny here, rather than encouraging consumers to pursue products with limited knowledge. Although it may successfully defend more restrictive regulation, as in the case of synthetic dyes. However, once we start justifying restrictions of individual freedom on the basis of public health, this may justify some of the very policies that the medical freedom movement criticizes.
Consider the previously alluded to ongoing measles outbreak in Texas. In an op-ed Kennedy emphasized that vaccination against measles is a personal choice, instead choosing to stress nutrition as the best way to combat the disease. But the data suggest encouraging vaccinations is a better policy than letting measles spread among even healthy people. In a longitudinal study of 276,327 doses of the MMR (mumps, measles, rubella) vaccine given to adults and adolescents from January 2010 to December 2018, there were fewer than 6 serious outcomes requiring hospitalization per 100,000 doses during the risk window following vaccination, some of which were attributable to patients’ prior health conditions. For comparison, measles cases in the United States from 1987–2000 led to hospitalizations at a rate of 19,200 per 100,000 cases and 300 deaths per 100,000 cases. If precaution can prevail over freedom, then this seems like as obvious a case as any; the movement ought to emphasize the importance of vaccines rather than individual choice.
But here Kennedy and members of the medical freedom movement opt for choice over public health. So, it is unclear exactly what value motivates them. Thus, members of the medical freedom movement should take a step back and ask themselves: What are we most committed to? If autonomy is their foundational commitment, then they should promote measures that increase choices available to the public while ensuring that they have plentiful access to information about the products that they consume. But if public health is their primary concern, then this would suggest policies that involve limiting individual choice in at least some respects and the policies that most effectively promote public health may be ones that they are likely to reject, such as promotion of mass vaccination.
As an outsider to decision making, it is easy to think you can have it all. But once forced to develop policy, one often finds that all values cannot be maximized simultaneously. In that case, one must choose which value has greater priority. By insisting on the importance of both public health and individual choice, the medical freedom movement fails to achieve either.