← Return to search results
Back to Prindle Institute

Why Follow the Law?

On December 4th, 2024 Luigi Mangione allegedly shot and killed a UnitedHealthcare CEO, and that action received impressively high levels of approval. More recently, critics of Musk and DOGE have been torching and vandalizing Teslas as an act of political protest. Even the current U.S. administration has shown disdain for the legal process, asserting new claims to executive power and pushing back against court orders. This growing disregard for legal norms raises an important question: Why follow the law?

The most straightforward reasons to follow the law are what we might consider practical or instrumental reasons. Of these, the most obvious is the fear of punishment – one should follow the law because, if they don’t, they will face certain consequences. There might also be clear self-interest at play. For example, laws such as using seatbelts and not drinking and driving provide decisive safety benefits to their followers and others on the road. Tax laws secure government resources, which can then be fed back into communities. Is there more than self-interest, though? If the only reasons to obey the law are instrumental, practical reasons, then if someone is, say, shielded from the consequences of breaking the law or thinks their lawbreaking will not be found out, why should they follow the law? It’s worth noting that if the only reason to follow a law is the fear of punishment — if that law truly provides no other public benefits — then that is the sign of a bad law.

One approach to answering the question of “why follow the law” are what philosophers call “transactional” theories of legal authority. The idea is that there is a transaction at play — the government provides something and, in exchange, participants in a political community incur an obligation to follow the law. The idea is simple enough with something like club membership. If you want to join the chess club, then you agree to follow the chess club’s rules. However, it is much more opaque with something like the law. Almost no one has actually meaningfully consented to be part of a country, they were just born that way. Though perhaps they would have given the choice. Philosophers sometimes appeal to hypothetical consent or implied rationality to argue that there is something like an agreement or contract between a nation and its residents. We might also consider a tacit agreement to follow the law based on the idea that the law, and the nation, provides a public good (even if specific individuals may benefit personally from breaking the law from time to time).

It follows from transactional approaches that governments must keep their side of the bargain. A corrupt and unjust government, or one that achieved power through illegitimate means (e.g., election fraud), incurs no special obligation for its people to obey its edicts.

Alternatively, we may think the obligation to follow the law flows from what it means to be a citizen or resident. Just as there may be virtues and obligations associated with being a student, a parent, or a nurse, being part of a political community comes with its own set of obligations and this could include an obligation to follow the law.

If laws are moral or practical, it is easy to justify our obedience. But what about unjust or immoral laws, is there still an obligation to follow those? Philosophers generally differ depending on what they think the law is. For philosophers in the natural law tradition, where laws are anchored in rights and privileges we have simply in being the kind of creature we are, an unjust law is no true law at all and cannot bind us. Other philosophers contend that laws flow instead from a social process. Instead of being rooted in morality, our obligation to follow the law comes from our deference to the legitimate procedure that shaped it. Still, a general obligation to follow unjust laws is likely overridden by more powerful and specific moral obligations. Moreover, one should perhaps question the political legitimacy of a nation which has a large number of unjust or otherwise deeply flawed laws.

Notably, none of this really accounts for the reasoning involved in burning Teslas or shooting CEOs. Very, very few philosophers would consider laws against property damage or murder unjust laws. Perpetrators may very well claim that their actions represent an attempt to prioritize the greater good, but the ability of greatest-good-for-the-greatest-number approaches in ethics to justify intuitively immoral actions has always been one of their most controversial features. (For more, see The Prindle Post’s discussions of the CEO killing and political violence.)

We may follow the law out of practicality, for moral reasons, to be a good citizen, or because we owe some general legal obligation to a politically legitimate state. However, just as morality can dovetail with the law, it can also push against it. Ideally, political obligation should come naturally. Laws should be generally accepted. They should make sense. They should feel fair. They should be applied equally. They should align with generally accepted moral norms. But if the law becomes an obstacle to achieving a life well lived, a weapon to be wielded against one’s political opponents, or a tool of oppression, then it is time to question the guidance the law offers and push for change.

Natural Law Theory and Human Rights Advocacy

photograph of stained glass depicting crowning of religious figure

In July 2019 Mike Pompeo announced the creation of a panel to examine the issue of human rights through the lens of natural law theory. This disquieted groups which advocate for LGBTQ rights and groups which advocate for abortion rights. Specifically, the Catholic theological connotations of the phrase “natural law” elicited significant negative response. Some media outlets provided minimal explanation about natural law theories, but little was written about what the alternative is to the natural law picture.

The connection to Catholic theology comes from the writings of Thomas Aquinas in his Summa Theologica. In his discussion of law, Aquinas specifies that there is an important connection between what two types of law which he identifies as “human law” and “natural law”. Human law is the body of explicit and authoritative rules put forth by governments and societies, while natural law is the rules of reasoning and action which apply to all thinking beings. In turn, these rules of reasoning and action are a subset of a third type of law that Aquinas calls “eternal law”—which are essentially the laws of physics, biology, psychology, sociology, etc. The argument of natural law theory, in brief, is that natural law serves as a yardstick of legitimacy for human laws. If a human edict contradicts natural law, then it is not really a law at all.

Enter the controversy. If human law must match with natural law, and if natural law entails prescriptions about human sexual and reproductive behavior, then human law must likewise make law directing human sexual and reproductive behavior. On this basis, academics like Mary Ann Glendon have argued against the inclusion of abortion as a human right. In her capacity as representative of the Vatican at a 1995 UN Conference on Women, Glendon argued that women’s sexual and reproductive rights are fundamentally rooted in duties to society, the lives of children, and God—rather than “… their own personal fulfillment …” In short, she means that any proposed legal right to abortion is not really a right at all because it contradicts natural law. Fast forward to 2019 and Glendon, a professor at Harvard Law School, is one of the academics who has been tapped to be on Pompeo’s human rights advisory committee. Her appointment is one of the aspects of the advisory committee that has worried advocates for LGBTQ and women’s rights.

But is it really natural law theory that is the problem? And if it is, what is the alternative? The usual contender with natural law theory is called legal positivism. The natural law theorist argues that human law, to count as a law at all, must measure up to some external standard. However, the legal positivist argues that to count as law a human edict need only be accepted as authoritative by the institutions which create and interpret it, as well as the subjects who follow it. The difference here is easy to miss, so take the example of laws establishing a right to seek an abortion. Mary Ann Glendon argued that such an alleged law is actually not a law at all, because it fails to meet the external standard of natural law. A legal positivist, like the 17th-century English philosopher Jeremy Bentham, would argue that if a law establishing a right to seek an abortion was issued by the proper legislative authority—and the people bound by that law habitually obey it—then it is a genuine law. This is true for the positivist even if the law fails to meet some external standard of morality or reasonability. This doesn’t mean that a positivist blindly accepts any law, no matter how repugnant—just that they acknowledge its status as the law of the land. (Incidentally, Bentham famously said “Natural rights is simple nonsense: natural and imprescriptible rights, rhetorical nonsense — nonsense upon stilts.” So some positivist theories would be no more welcoming to the idea of a right to seek an abortion, than Gledon’s version of natural law theory.)

Advocates for LGTBQ and women’s rights may not be best interpreted as positivists, however. In general, the language of human rights invokes something more like natural law theory. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights, which is the touchstone document on the subject of human rights for advocates worldwide, speaks of “…  the inherent dignity and of the equal and inalienable rights of all members of the human family …” continuing that these” … should be protected by the rule of law.” This language indicates that human rights exist before law, and that the law serves to enshrine or protect an externally determined standard. Further, laws protecting the gamut of human rights are represented as necessary parts of the laws of any civilized and just nation. This matches closely with the Thomas Aquinas’ view that there are some human laws which are simply demanded by the natural law.

Whatever the merits or ulterior motives of Pompeo’s Commission on Unalienable Rights, natural law theory itself is not inimical to the cause of LGBTQ and women’s rights. Such a theory even seems to be a fundamental underpinning of the worldwide advocacy of fundamental human rights.

Judd v Weinstein: Reexamining Ex Post Facto

Photograph of a gavel next to two large books

In the United States hundreds of new laws come into effect every year at both the state and federal level. Some of these laws criminalize actions that were once legal, while others simply serve to reform the existing judicial system. The concept of retroactive punishment has been a concept debated in the philosophy of law since the beginning of time. At the heart of this debate lies the relationship between the law and morality as well as the purpose of the law itself. One recent example which demonstrates the tension between the law and morality is Ashley Judd’s lawsuit against Harvey Weinstein. In the case, Judd cites a law which prohibits sexual harassment of the nature which Judd is alleging. However, Judge Philip S. Gutierrez dismissed this charge because, at the time of the alleged harassment, late 1996 to early 1997, the law cited did not extend to producers such as Weinstein. While Judd is still able to pursue a defamation charge against Weinstein, the dismissal of the harassment allegations seems troubling, especially considering Weinstein’s current legal standing with sexual harassment and assault. Was it wrong for Gutierrez to dismiss the charges? Should a person be punished for an act that was not illegal at the time that it was committed? And is the purpose of the law inherently tied to morality?

The allegations against Weinstein that began in 2017 not only ushered in the #MeToo movement, but also posed questions about the ties between the law and morality. In one specific case, Ashley Judd vs Harvey Weinstein, Weinstein’s actions toward Judd, which include harassment of a sexual nature while he was in a position of power over Judd, were found to be legal for Weinstein at the time that he committed them. Despite the fact that Weinstein’s actions would be illegal today, a judge found that he could not be charged with these allegations in the present. The inapplicability of retroactive laws, otherwise known as ex post facto, is an important concept in the philosophy of law. An ex post facto law is defined as “a criminal statute that punishes actions retroactively, thereby criminalizing conduct that was legal when originally performed.” Currently, there are two statutes in the United States Constitution that prohibit ex post facto laws, Art 1, § 9 and Art. 1 § 10

The prohibition of ex post facto laws is not unique to the U.S. with many countries observing the unjust nature of such laws. In fact, the illegitimacy of ex post facto shares widespread support in part due to its prevalence in U.S. courts since the 18th century. U.S. Supreme case Calder v. Bull (1798) established the fundamental aspects of ex post facto laws including laws that “create or aggravate the crime or increase the punishment or change the rules of evidence for the purpose of conviction.

A more recent Supreme Court decision which is often cited is that of Beazell v Ohio (1925). In this case, the majority held that “any statute which punishes as a crime an act previously committed, which was innocent when done, which makes more burdensome the punishment for a crime, after its commission, or which deprives one charged with crime of any defense available according to law at the time when the act was committed, is prohibited as ex post facto.” Ex post facto is not only considered essential to the integrity of the judicial system but can also be argued for on the basis of morality.

While one might admit that Weinstein’s actions were morally wrong, one could ultimately hold that it is unjust to punish him for an act he committed that was (unfortunately) legal at the time. Punishing him might set a bad precedent that would essentially undermine the value that laws hold. Why even pass new laws making sexual harassment illegal if one can be punished without the laws taking effect? On the other hand, proponents of punishing Weinstein would argue that what makes Weinstein deserving of punishment in this case is the abhorrent and immoral nature of his actions. If the purpose of law is to either punish those who deserve to be punished or contribute to the welfare of society, then Weinstein could be justifiably be punished either way. But can we truly pick and choose which actions justify ex post facto and which do not? If I were to buy cigarettes today and it becomes illegal to purchase cigarettes in 2 weeks, should I be punished for the time I bought cigarettes? What if I were to prank-call my neighbor? Or drive the speed limit in the fast lane? Though these scenarios are small, they all demonstrate that it seems silly and unreasonable to apply ex post facto punishments in every situation, but it also becomes hard to draw the line in which cases are appropriate. The judge’s logic in this case as well as the general attitude that law and morality should stay separate is relatively popular within legal positivism.

On the other hand, some proponents of natural law might argue that retroactive laws can and should indeed be enforced. This is because the justification for punishment stems not only from the breaking of a man-made law, but also a moral law. Though an act might not have been illegal within code, it is still against the fundamental moral laws reinforced by a higher power. Debates about ex post facto laws were especially prevalent during the international Nuremberg trials of Nazi war criminals. The state of international law during the Nazi era did not indicate an illegality of some of the most morally repugnant actions of Nazis at the time, including the Holocaust. Regardless of this fact, many in the international political and judicial community felt that officials in the Nazi regime should be punished for their crimes against humanity. However, not everyone agreed, including Jewish legal scholars, such as United States federal judge Charles Wyzanski Jr., who stressed the violation of the ex post facto principle in several cases during the Nuremberg trials. But perhaps, to many people, the decision to punish Nazis for every morally reprehensible act they committed is necessary and just regardless of the circumstances. If the purpose of law is to punish, prevent future crime, or both, it seems that there are many instances, Weinstein’s included, that could morally merit the application of ex post facto punishment.

Though Judd will not be able to pursue sexual harassment charges against Weinstein, many others are successfully pursuing their cases of sexual assault against Weinstein at a trial in New York in 2019. While many would argue that Weinstein’s harassment of Judd should have been illegal in the first place, it is also possible to recognize the importance of upholding the integrity of the law and the ex post facto principle. As we continue to modify and enhance laws against sexual harassment, one can hope that cases such as Judd’s find proper legal and moral justice in the future.