← Return to search results
Back to Prindle Institute
Science

Is There a Problem With Scientific Discoveries Made by Harassers?

By Eric Walker
6 Dec 2017

The question about bias in science is in the news again.

It arose before, in the summer, when the press got hold of an inflammatory internal memo that Google employees had been circulating around their company. The memo’s author, James Damore, now formerly of Google, argued that Google’s proposed solutions to eradicating the gender gap in software engineering are flawed. They’re flawed, Damore thought, because they assume that the preponderance of men in “tech and leadership positions” is a result only of social and institutional biases, and they ignore evidence from evolutionary psychology suggesting that biologically inscribed differences in “personality,” “interests,” and “preferences” explain why women tend not to hold such positions.

The status of evolutionary psychology as a science is controversial: many observers are skeptical of its ambition to explain modern moral, political, and cultural phenomena by reference to ancient pre-moral, pre-political, and pre-cultural evolutionary patterns. Since Damore’s memo drew freely from articles in this field, and cited those articles in support of what many deemed as unsavory ideas, these same observers were prompted to publicly reexamine what it takes for any field of inquiry to count as scientifically respectable, what it means for science to be objective, and the extent to which science generally, or evolutionary psychology specifically, is a reliable source of knowledge.

And now bias in the sciences — be they aspiring or mature — is a philosophical issue again, but the conversation has adopted a slightly different tone and target.

The recent spate of sexual harassment allegations brought against prominent men in media and entertainment has raised anew the question of whether the artistic fruits of a morally suspect artist are irredeemably tainted by their having been produced by a morally suspect artist. (See this collection of essays for a wide range of responses to this question.)

A seemingly analogous question has risen about science and technology: “Can We Still Rely on Science Done by Sexual Harassers?” In this Wired article, Adam Rogers asks about the attitude we should take toward theories, discoveries, and innovations that are articulated, made, and founded by scientists who engage in morally suspect behavior.

It’s a good question to ask, and a timely one, especially given recent allegations of sexual harassment by a noted Antarctic researcher. But while the aesthetic and epistemic questions look like they have a common structure, we should take care to see whether they can be answered in the same way.

A potentially important difference is that works of art are meant to be savored and lingered over, while theories and technological innovations are meant to be believed and relied upon. When we ask about the relationship between a morally suspect artist and his work, we’re implicitly asking philosophical questions such as: “What’s the connection, if any, between my reasons for savoring a work of art and my reasons for condemning its originator?,” “Do my reasons for savoring the work always or automatically get outweighed by my reasons for condemning its creator?,” and “Do my reasons for savoring the work even survive the discovery of the artist’s moral corruption?”

But when we ask about the relationship between a morally suspect scientist and his results, we’re implicitly asking philosophical questions such as “What’s the connection, if any, between my reasons for believing in these results and my reasons for condemning their originator?,” “Do my reasons for believing in the results always or automatically get outweighed by my reasons for condemning their originator?,” and “Do my reasons for believing in the result even survive the discovery of the scientist’s moral corruption?”  

When these sub-questions are teased apart from the larger questions they compose, many might see a glaring difference between the larger questions. Many might conclude, that is, that moral unscrupulousness has less effect on what we should believe than on what we should savor. Our reasons for believing in, say, the existence of a newly discovered exoplanet are more immune to its discoverer’s moral corruption than are our reasons for savoring, say, the sexually explicit jokes crafted by a sexual predator. After all, the personality of the artist seems discernible in his work in a way that the personality of the scientist seems not: the joke, you might think, intimates the taste and outlook of its creator — however indirectly or ironically — while the planet is just there, no matter how depraved its discoverer is.

But all science might not be so cleanly separated from the scientist. What many might deem distasteful androcentric biases in primatology, for example, can lead to results lacking the proper epistemic credentials.

In general, when observing primate behavior, primatologists have tended to adopt the perspective of males, seeing female behavior in light of, and as furthering, male interests. But fruitful hypotheses about primate behavior have emerged by reversing things and adopting the perspective of females, seeing male behavior in light of, and as furthering, female interests.

Moreover, in particular, primatology since Darwin has been dominated by a model of sexual selection, according to which “eager males compete with one another for access to choosy, reticent females.” The model has trouble explaining female promiscuity in primates — an undeniable pattern of behavior that has hitherto remained mysterious — because one of its underlying assumptions is that the only evolutionary benefit of sex for a female is to gather sperm from a high-quality male.

Assuming that female interests are best understood in light of male ones, and that females are primarily selective sperm receptacles, has not only hampered research but has made the androcentric hypotheses look like the only hypotheses in the offing. And believing in a hypothesis that hasn’t competed with other hypotheses is irresponsible, epistemically speaking. The reasons for believing in a lone hypothesis can weaken once competing hypotheses are on the table. So the reasons for condemning an androcentric primatologist can bear on the reasons for believing in his theory.

In the tech world, the connection between the immoral biases of the researcher and the reliability of his invention can be even tighter. As Rogers so aptly describes it, in the field of artificial intelligence and machine learning, “programmers choose when to tell the machine when it has gotten something right or wrong.” The definition of success “will be skewed to whatever the designer of the algorithm thinks matters.” In this way, the values of the inventor become embedded in what’s invented. (The ineradicability of human judgment in machine learning and computational analysis often gets ignored.)

For example, an algorithm that is built to assess the actuarial fitness of health insurance applicants, but whose default model is a household consisting of a man, a woman, and their kids, can’t be relied upon for assessing a household consisting of, for example, two men and their kids.

In science and technology, then, some cases offer no easy separation between the value of the fruits of human ingenuity and the behavior or character of the humans who bear those fruits. Whether this makes science and technology more like art or less like art is an open question.

Eric Walker is a doctoral candidate in philosophy at the University of California, Riverside, writing a dissertation articulating the sense in which a formal symbolism serves as a medium for mathematical investigation. He teaches German idealism, romanticism, existentialism, phenomenology, ethics and the meaning in life, art and aesthetics, formal and informal reasoning, the history of analytic philosophy, and the history and philosophy of science, mathematics, logic, and technology.
Related Stories